Philosophy For Dummies. Tom Morris
Читать онлайн книгу.that, even if all its premises were true, its conclusion could still be false.
With inductive logic, the truth of the premises just raises the probability of, or renders more likely, or gives evidential support to, the conclusion, without giving a 100-percent guarantee that it is true. Here is an example of inductive reasoning:
(1) All objects of type A that we have seen have had property B.
(2) There is likely nothing atypical about any A-type objects not yet seen.
Therefore, probably,
(3) The next A that we see will have property B.
Inductive logic is not as ironclad as deductive reasoning, but it is the basis for most science and technology, and has achieved tremendous results.
The standard philosophical analysis of knowledge presents it as nothing more, or less, than properly justified true belief. The concept of justification here is that of rational justification. So philosophers have asked throughout the centuries, “What is required for rational justification?” The question is what might be needed to support a belief if that conviction is to have a chance of qualifying as knowledge. And the question can be put in other ways: What makes a belief rational or reasonable to hold? What indicators of truth does rationality demand?
There are people who seem to think that something like strict logical proof is required for rationality. Their mantra is “Prove it.” An old friend, who was a distinguished professor at Yale, once recounted that he had received an unexpected phone call from his son’s Sunday School teacher. The man had reported, “Professor, every time I say anything new in our class, your little boy blurts out, ‘Prove it!’ Could you please have a talk with him and explain that no one can prove everything?” My friend had to laugh and go have a chat with his demanding young rationalist. As the philosopher John Locke concluded from his own research into the nature of proof, “He that, in the ordinary affairs of life, would admit of nothing but direct plain demonstration would be sure of nothing in this world but of perishing quickly.” Solid proof, or in Locke’s language, demonstration in life is rare and so is not ordinarily required.
It seems clearly excessive to think that no belief is rational to hold unless the believer is in possession of some decisive and compelling proof that it’s true. You have beliefs about the galaxy, nuclear energy, your computer, and even your own body that you can’t prove in any decisive sense. You can most often produce some bit of evidence, or the reported testimony of some expert, or at least a vague memory of having once had either evidence or testimony for the truth of what you believe, but you are rarely in possession of a knock-down, incontrovertible proof. Life just doesn’t work like that.
As a result of this realization, some philosophers have suggested that perhaps it is excessive to require proof for rationality, but it may indeed be necessary to have at least sufficient evidence in order to be justified in believing anything.
On this philosophy, widely known as evidentialism, it is irrational ever to believe anything without sufficient evidence that it’s true. Hearsay is not enough, sheer faith is never alone to be trusted, and an unsupported intuition is not admissible at all. Hard evidence or nothing is the demand. But this may itself not be a reasonable demand. Rational belief may not even always dependent on evidence. And that’s a surprise to many people. It’s a matter that Chapter 5 in this book explores.
Philosophy involves an exploration of the biggest questions about human life and its context, as well as a determined search to find answers. Any possible answer or belief on these big issues must be assessed carefully for its truth, and that most often means examining any evidence or argument or any other serious consideration we can find that might indicate its truth. And this requires logical thinking. Logic is vital. You can’t just go with a hunch or a feeling, but have to test ideas logically, first to understand them fully, and then to evaluate them well. It will take you on one of the most unusual intellectual journeys of your life to answer the biggest, deepest questions about evidence and rationality and what logical scrutiny can tell us about them, a journey to be undertaken in the next two chapters. So, if you’re up to it, buckle up your mental seat belt, keep reading, and prepare for the philosophical ride of your life.
Chapter 5
The Challenge of Skepticism
IN THIS CHAPTER
Looking at the ancient challenge of skepticism
Asking some of the deepest questions ever
Understanding when to doubt, and when to doubt our doubts
Discovering one of the most important principles of rationality
Doubt is the vestibule which all must pass, before they can enter into the temple of truth.
— Charles Caleb Colton (1825)
We live in a culture awash in information. We’re drowning in data each day. The media trumpet that, with the advent of modern communications and advanced technology, human knowledge is expanding geometrically faster than at any other period in history. Some say knowledge at least doubles every four years now. Others claim the growth of what we know is even faster.
But the question is whether we really know all that we think we know and whether all this new information really amounts to knowledge or not. You can easily come to wonder if it’s precisely knowledge that is expanding, or just belief, or perhaps mere opinion. The constant and rapid flow of apparent information into our lives may lull us into thinking we have increasingly more knowledge, when actually we may be gaining nothing of the kind. We may not know even a fraction of what we think we know. In this chapter, we look at the most ancient challenge to our claim to have knowledge, and we actually discover from it some deep and important insights we all need.
Since the ancient world, philosophers have cautioned about humankind’s natural tendency to claim knowledge where knowledge, in fact, may not exist. The ancient philosophy of skepticism can help you to understand more deeply what exactly knowledge is, and where it comes from, as well as to answer the open question philosophers have often asked of whether evidence is always required for rational belief, and thus for knowledge.
In this chapter, you will see how the most basic form of skeptical inquiry can give a fresh perspective on the foundations of all human knowledge. You’ll be introduced to some fundamental questions you’ve likely never asked, and in the process of trying to answer them, you’ll discover an overlooked principle of rationality. This just may be the most philosophically challenging chapter in the whole book, but if you can grasp its reasoning and its implications, you’ll see all the other issues of philosophy in a new way. The questions that are raised by skepticism can put everything in a new light, and can inspire you with a needed humility and deeper perspective concerning all claims to knowledge.
Introducing the Ancient Art of Doubt
The words skeptic and skepticism come from an ancient Greek verb that meant “to inquire.” Etymologically, then, a skeptic is an inquirer. This should form an important background insight for your understanding of skeptical doubt. Skepticism at its best is not a matter of denial, but of inquiring, seeking, questioning doubt. As long ago as Homer’s Odyssey, we find the striking exclamation: “How prone to doubt, how cautious are the