Human Rights. Michael Freeman
Читать онлайн книгу.Slotte 2015).
Samuel Moyn has argued that the ‘deep history’ of human rights, tracing the contemporary concept back to the eighteenth century and beyond, is false. The concept of human rights, on his account, refers to a global morality that became significant only in the 1970s. Earlier conceptions of rights were addressed to different problems and thus had different meanings. For example, the eighteenth-century French revolutionary concept of the Rights of Man affirmed the sovereignty of the nation-state, whereas the concept of human rights seeks to constrain state sovereignty by appealing to a normative order above the state. The earlier concepts could not therefore be the source of the later one. This is the true history of human rights. Moyn believes that the contemporary human-rights movement seeks legitimacy in this false deep history and its supposed inevitability. He admits that there is some continuity in the history of human rights but holds that the discontinuities are more important than the continuities, because they emphasize the role of choice in history, thereby keeping open the possibility of better choices in future (Moyn 2010).
Moyn’s ‘discontinuity’ objection to ‘textbook’ histories of human rights is distinct from the ‘triumphalist’ objection. ‘Deep’ history can, however, be defended against both objections. As a history of Christianity would be absurd without a reference to the life of Jesus, so a history of human rights can be illuminated by tracing its ancient origins. Such an approach does not have to deny the obvious fact that the meaning of rights-language has changed over time, that rights-proposals have often been contested, that the history is one of advances and setbacks, paths taken and opportunities missed, of main roads, side roads and dead ends. The history should assume as little as possible about the merits and limitations of the contemporary concept: evaluation belongs to philosophy not history (see chapter four).
However, before we can study the history of human rights, we must know what it is the history of. We might begin with a definition, but the variety of meanings of human rights across time and space makes an uncontroversial definition difficult. It is better, therefore, to begin the history of human rights with the point of the concept. The contemporary concept of human rights was developed as a response to the abuse of power. This conception of human rights is suitable for deep history because power and its abuse can be found throughout history. The history of human rights can trace the emergence of the idea of universal rights as a solution to this problem. The modern concept differs from earlier rights-concepts, but it is composed of various elements that have their own histories and that have come together in the modern concept.
Some say that the concept of human rights has a universal history. The Code of Hammurabi (c.1792–1750 bc), king of Babylon, is said to be the oldest surviving text establishing the rule of law. Cyrus the Great (died 529 bc), king of Persia, proclaimed a policy of religious toleration and abolished slavery. The Buddhist King Ashoka of India (c.264–238 bc) also promoted religious toleration, provided for the health and education of his people, and appointed officials to prevent wrongful punishments (Weeramantry 1997: 7–8). Thus, principles now associated with human rights can be found in ancient times in many cultures. These examples weaken the claim that the concept of human rights is Western. However, they appear to be evidence of benevolent rulers rather than of human rights as such.
Others maintain that the concept of human rights originated in the West and was universalized only recently. Some argue that, if the history is Western, its validity cannot be universal. Others say that the history of a concept is irrelevant to its validity: there may be good reasons for universalizing a concept that has a particular history.
Some have argued that there could be no concept of individual rights in ancient times, because individuals were considered to be subordinate parts of the social whole. This idea was weakened by increasing social complexity that undermined roles and identities, creating the rights-bearing individual. This historical sociology of individual rights is supposed to discredit the concept of universal human rights. But is it true?
On rights and tyrants
The ancient Greeks are credited with the invention of several concepts that will later play a crucial role in the concept of human rights: the human individual with a mind and a soul; universal truth; the fundamental value of human beings (humanism) (Snell 1953). Whether or not the ancient Greeks had a concept of ‘rights’, they certainly had the concepts of power and its abuse. This was expressed in the concept of tyranny, which was a form of arbitrary (lawless) government, in which the ruler governed in his own interest and treated his people unjustly. It was possible, however, for the Greeks to think about tyranny without talking about rights. In Sophocles’ play Antigone, the king forbids Antigone to bury her dead brother because he had been a rebel. Antigone defies the king’s order, but on the ground that she has a religious duty to bury her brother, not on the ground that she has a right to do so. We might see Sophocles’ play as a human-rights drama about the right to freedom of religion, but Sophocles did not express it this way.
Aristotle believed that constitutions could assign rights, such as the rights to property and participation in public affairs, to citizens. When these rights were violated, the laws determined compensation or punishment. Aristotle had no conception of human rights, however, as he believed that rights derived from constitutions, and that some men were slaves by nature (Miller, F. 1995).
Justice and rights
Roman law provides the main link between classical Greek thought about rights and modern conceptions through its influence on medieval ideas. The French historian, Michel Villey, initiated a debate on the distinction between objective right (that which is right) and subjective rights (personal entitlements). Villey argued that Roman law had no conception of subjective rights: the Latin word ius referred to objective right (Tuck 1979: 7–9; Tierney 1988: 4–6, 15). Villey’s view has been questioned on the ground that Roman law conceived of justice as rendering to each his right (suum ius). Other scholars have found rights to property, freedom from arbitrary rule, and fair trial in Roman law. These were not human rights but the legal rights of citizens; non-citizens and slaves were excluded. Slaves were recognized as persons and given some limited protection by the law, but they could not make complaints in court and there was no ideological objection to slavery. Roman law also recognized the law of nations as law common to all peoples – an important precursor of modern international law (Giltaij and Tuori 2015).
The Stoic philosophers believed in a universal moral community, governed by a common natural law. It is, however, doubtful whether they had the concept of human rights, although there is some scholarly disagreement on this point (Sorabji 1993; Mitsis 1999: 176–7). Cicero held that everyone had a duty not to harm anyone else but he did not express this in terms of natural rights but of duties deriving from an objective right order based on natural law common to all rational beings (Atkins 2018: 44).
The Stoic philosophy influenced early Christianity, which provided a new basis for the unity underlying the diversity of peoples. Christians saw the salvation of the individual soul as the highest good. The duty to seek salvation presupposed the autonomy of the individual will, which derived its dignity from the will of God. However, although Christianity separated the demands it made of the individual from those made by society, St Paul preached obedience to secular political authority. Christianity also preached the ‘love of the poor’. Although salvation might be available only to an elite, all humans were morally equal in that each was a candidate for salvation: women as well as men. The Christian author, Tertullian, wrote around 217 ad that it was ‘a basic human right that everyone should be free to worship according to his own convictions’ (Wiles and Santer 1977: 227). A decree of the emperor Charlemagne, dated 802 ad, speaks of the rights (justitias) of the people, especially of the poor, the widows and the orphans (Nelson 2019: 396–7). Eventually, the idea emerged that secular laws were not legitimate if they contravened the laws of God. The Church, however, largely conformed to the norms of society, accepting existing social hierarchies, the patriarchal family and slavery.
A clear shift from objective right to subjective rights took place in the late Middle Ages. Medieval people