Law, Language, and Empire in the Roman Tradition. Clifford Ando
Читать онлайн книгу.my own concern is not with the vastly important questions, in what venues and in what forms the civil law was applied around the empire, or even how its content was known to subjects of Rome. My goal is rather to isolate and study the effects on legal philosophy and legal reasoning that arose from the civil law’s implication in those contexts. This again falls outside traditional forms of intellectual-historical inquiry practiced in the field.
To sketch in brief compass two proposals central to what follows, to understand the civil law as an instrument of empire and the product of an imperial state means first situating Roman civil law in all its jurisdictions alongside other codes of law; it requires us to view the Roman Empire, even Rome itself, as legally pluralist; it compels us to understand the operations of law in light of the discrepant legal statuses of the persons whose lives it regulated; and it demands that we recall the populations of the empire to have been linguistically, culturally, and in every other respect heterogenous.
Second, we need to remember that the civil law was at different times and in different ways called upon to codify and sustain systems of differential legal privilege: civil-law arguments were adduced to justify the acquisition of empire, even as civil-law actions were devised and deployed to consolidate its fruits.
This volume is also intended as a celebration of the astonishing creativity of the lawyers and jurists who wrote and reasoned the law at Rome. To read and think in their company is to encounter those ancients who grappled most sincerely and most extensively with the complexity and diversity of the world ancient political action had brought into being. What follows is often a critical reading, but throughout an appreciative one.
Chapter 1
Citizen and Alien before the Law
The object of this chapter is to excavate a body of law that does not exist, namely, the one that governed aliens, particularly aliens in dispute with citizens or with aliens of discrepant citizenship, before Roman courts. In doing so, I hope to advance four interrelated claims beyond the particular work of recuperation I shall perform in respect to legal practice.
First, I urge that a number of the most distinctive formal mechanisms in Roman law and legal language—most notably the fiction and its kin—were developed precisely in order to accommodate before the law persons and things notionally excluded by jurisdictional rules. Second, these mechanisms are visible in statutory language long before they are taken up in jurisprudence and, not surprisingly, they do their most interesting work in the early period of Roman law exactly at those moments and in those places where the Romans sought to incorporate juridically non-Roman populations within their state, namely, in the experimental colonial and provincial landscapes of Greece and Africa in the late second century B.C.E., in the municipalities of Italy created de novo as Roman communities in the aftermath of the Social War, and the reorganization of Cisalpine Gaul after the extension of citizenship to its residents and its statutory redescription as part of Italy.
Third, in the hands of the jurists of the classical period, these mechanisms are redeployed to resolve an historically new but structurally similar problem, namely, the resolution of apparent conflicts of law. These arose for the jurists of the classical period prior to the Antonine Constitution principally through the operation at Rome of multiple sources of law: statute, as issued by an assembly of the citizen body; praetorian edict; and imperial utterance. Although these rose to prominence in the order in which they are here listed, none was understood to have superseded the others or, more precisely, none was understood in the classical period to have gone into abeyance or to have ceased functioning altogether. In consequence, despite the existence within Roman legal philosophy of doctrines of desuetude, jurists were reluctant to describe laws from these varied sources as having radically superseded each other. Rather, later laws are described as honoring the principles articulated in earlier legislation, even as they worked in precise but significant ways to subvert those same principles. For that delicate task, the fiction was an ideal tool.
Fourth and last, confrontation with the complicated legal landscapes created by the work of empire and Rome’s own complex past spurred the development by Roman jurists and legislators alike of two distinctive traditions that have since proved fundamental to the history of the civil law, in its work both in Europe and abroad, namely, a remarkable historical selfconsciousness on the one hand, and a foundational concern for the capacity of legal language to give normative description to the worlds it was called upon to regulate on the other.
Citizenship and Jurisdiction: Ius Civile Defined
When I say that the substantive law governing relations between citizen and alien does not exist, I intend the claim in both an historical and a normative sense. At the level of history, the vast bulk of the legal texts that survive from the Roman world were selected and edited for their contemporary utility by scholars working in the sixth century C.E., some three hundred years after the universalization of citizenship. Apart from the trace evidence of a few titles of works quoted exclusively for their civil-law content, such substantive law as once existed to govern citizen-alien relations had long since lost any relevance and was rigorously excluded from the late ancient codifications.
In ideological terms, Roman lawyers understood, and Roman legislators betimes required, civil-law actions to be available exclusively to Roman citizens. Significant moments in this history include laws of 95 B.C.E., the socalled lex Licinia Mucia, and another passed by Augustus, called by ancient and modern scholars the lex Iulia iudiciaria (these are cited by sources in the Appendix, in passages 6D and 9, respectively).1 The principle at stake was given decisive formulation in the second century C.E. in Gaius’s Institutes, in concise wording that bespeaks a common understanding:
All peoples who are governed by statutes and customs observe partly their own peculiar law and partly the common law of all human beings. The law that each people establishes for itself is peculiar to it, and is called ius civile (nam quod quisque populus ipse sibi ius constituit, id ipsius proprium est vocaturque ius civile), being, as it were, the special law of that civitas, that community of citizens, while the law that natural reason establishes among all human beings is followed by all peoples alike, and is called ius gentium, being, as it were, the law observed by all peoples. Thus the Roman people observes partly its own peculiar law and partly the common law of humankind. (Gaius Inst. 1.1; the Latin text of the whole may be found in Appendix passage 1.)
A civil law is thus the body of law that a community of citizens establishes for and over itself; and access to its actions is largely expected to be restricted to the members of that community, namely, its citizens. The heart of Gaius’s claim might thus be said to rest in the distributive quisque and reflexive sibi: every civitas makes a ius civile for itself.2 (As a corollary, it would seem that any political community worthy of the name would have such a body of law.)
This principle of law and legal theory has an important correlate in the fundamental place granted to contractarianism in Roman political thought. In this tradition, a political collectivity, a populus, is formed through the consensual commitment of its members to a particular normative order. According to Cicero, for example, “a people is not any coming-together of human beings, herded together for any reason whatsoever, but a coming-together of many iuris consensu, united by consensual commitment to a particular normative order and common utility” (De re publica 1.39; see Appendix passage 2). Alternatively, in a formulation widely cited by late medieval lawyers, a populus is a collectio multorum ad iure vivendum; quae nisi iure vivat, non est populus, “a gathering of many in order to live according to law, which, if it does not live according to law, is not a populus.”3 Chapter 5 in this volume essays to describe the worlds in which this formulation circulated and whose political cultures it functioned to describe.
The distinctiveness and pervasiveness of this Roman commitment to contractarianism is visible above all in the common use of civitas, citizenship, as a metonym for both city and political community. The corresponding term in Greek, politeia, which can mean citizenship or governing order, interanimates no such cluster of concepts. The ability