The Wiley-Blackwell Handbook of Childhood Social Development. Группа авторов

Читать онлайн книгу.

The Wiley-Blackwell Handbook of Childhood Social Development - Группа авторов


Скачать книгу

      In this chapter we first revisit the philosophical foundation of developmental thinking and its application to understanding children. This brings the reader to the great German philosopher Kant, and to the founder of child development and education, Rousseau. In particular, Rousseau’s book on the boy Émile will be presented as the core publication of modern thoughts on childhood and education, followed by the reception of this book by historical founders of developmental psychology and pedagogy in Germany, Switzerland, and The Netherlands.

      After the explanation of the role of Enlightenment thinking in terms of “progress” and development, it will be made clear that one essential feature of the Enlightenment philosophy is disputable: the unjustified belief in “progress.” This idea of “progress” is fully present in the original developmental ideas of Rousseau, and also of his later follower Piaget. It will be explained in this chapter that neo‐ and post‐neo‐Piagetian research essentially leads us back to the insight that children are serious interlocutors at a much younger age than we have been inclined to think since the Rousseau‐Piaget tradition (Koops, 2016).

      Finally, it will be concluded that the study of the cultural history of childhood and child development makes clear that child development is less (biologically) continuous than has been the assumption since Rousseau. Post‐neo‐Piagetian research (for example about the Child’s Theory of Mind), makes clear that children are much more serious, if not adult, interlocutors. We may speak of a historical reframing of childhood, with numerous new possibilities for pedagogy and education.

Photo depicts the statue of Immanuel Kant (1724–1804). Photo depicts Jean Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778).

      Source: Allan Ramsay, Jean‐Jacques Rousseau, National Gallery of Scotland).

      What message did Rousseau wish to convey? He claimed that pedagogy should be child‐oriented; that there are age‐related stages, to which the approach towards the child, including the pedagogical and educational approach, must be tailored; and that children must only be offered knowledge when they display a need for it. Moreover, knowledge must spring from a child’s own explorations, from hands‐on experience, preferably not from books. A child should certainly not be exposed to wisdom from books before the age of 12! Despite much enthusiasm, from Kant among others, Rousseau’s book should in the first place be regarded as a revolutionary Enlightenment text, not as a pedagogical handbook. His book stemmed from the tradition which Israel (2001, 2005) named “radical Enlightenment.”

      According to Israel, the key figure of this radical Enlightenment is Baruch Spinoza (16321677), the great Dutch philosopher. The “Epilogue” of Israel’s book is entitled: “Rousseau, radicalism, revolution.” Spinoza by way of Denis Diderot (17131784) led to Rousseau and the French revolution. The Émile was indeed radical. In the Émile the author pointed out that he did not only rebel against French society, but also and foremost against its reproduction (Soëtard, 1989, p. 97). Rousseau thought that children should be taken “back to nature” (however, this expression did not appear in his writings, but in those of his commentators). With “back to nature” Rousseau meant: as far away as possible from Parisian decadence. Children should learn to think autonomously, without being led astray by French culture, without following other people’s wisdom from books. This Enlightenment idea is the radical expression of the primacy of the autonomously thinking individual, which had great appeal to Kant. And this is the reason that Rousseau’s Émile is a book for philosophers, not for educationalists, fathers and mothers, as Rousseau emphasized (Bloom, 1979, p. 28). However, to no avail!


Скачать книгу